Nicht aus der Schweiz? Besuchen Sie lehmanns.de

Hegel-Studien, Bd. 56

Buch | Softcover
254 Seiten
2022 | 1. Auflage
Meiner (Verlag)
978-3-7873-4367-6 (ISBN)

Lese- und Medienproben

Hegel-Studien, Bd. 56 -
CHF 179,20 inkl. MwSt
  • Versand in 10-15 Tagen
  • Versandkostenfrei
  • Auch auf Rechnung
  • Artikel merken
FORTSETZUNG Rainer Enskat: Die Form der Dialektik in Hegels Phänomenologie des Geistes
Abstract:
In his Phenomenology of Spirit Hegel has – in comparison with the enormous
complexity of the whole work – in a somewhat hidden way hinted at the formal nucleus of what
he conceives of as dialectic, especially as the dialectical movement. This movement has the form
of a sceptical examination, testing the claims of the consciousness to be in the possession of
knowledge. Such a claim is bound, as Hegel shows, to many different cognitive levels of the
consciousness – beginnig with sensual certainty and ending with absolute knowledge. The way
of the examination corresponds exactly to the levels of the consciousness. But on its way to the
absolute knowledge the examination encounters, appropriate to its sceptical intention, as many
non-veracious forms of knowledge as are different from absolute knowledge. Each sceptical test
which encounters a non-veracious form of knowledge presents necessarily the nothingness of
what it is the result, a result which contains what the foregoing non-veracious forms of
knowledge save anyhowas true. In the following article it is to show that this nucleus of the form
of the dialectical movement stands the test ifapplied to the step resp. jump from sensual certainty
to perception. If the following interpretationsand analysesare founded well enough it is justified
to be confident that interpretations and analyses of further ‘experiences of consciousness’ on the
same line can be fruitful.
Bernardo Ferro: How Platonic is Hegel’s Dialectic? A new approach to an old debate
Abstract:
While in recent years the link between Hegel and Aristotle has been widely
explored, Hegel’s Platonic heritage seems to have faded into the background. This asymmetry is
partly due to the standard characterization of Plato as a dogmatic metaphysician, committed to a
“two-world” ontology. In this paper, I show that Hegel’s engagement with Plato stands out
precisely for his rejection of this kind of reading and, moreover, that this attitude sheds an
important light on his own thought. To determine how, I focus on Plato’s and Hegel’s conceptions
of dialectics. I argue that both models, despite their obvious differences, share key
structural similarities, which can only be truly appreciated by moving beyond mainstream Platonism.
This change of perspective allows for a clearer understanding of Hegel’s philosophical
development and for new insights into his philosophy as a whole.
Anton Friedrich Koch: Hegel’s Parmenidean Descent to the Science Without Contrary
Abstract:
This essay is intended to make Hegel’s Science of Logic intelligible from its basic antidogmatic
methodological rule and resolve: “to want to think purely”, i. e. without presuppositions.
The beginning of the Logic (with Being, Nothing, Becoming, Being-there) is deduced from this
resolve in detail, as is the central logical operation of negation, especially in application to itself,
i. e. non-well-founded or circular negation. Various forms of negation in the logic of being and
the three basic types of circular negation that are operative in the logic of being, essence and
concept respectively are distinguished and all findings are related to Hegel’s text. The discussion
takes place within the framework of classical metaphysics and logic (Plato, Aristotle, Leibniz) and
contemporary analytic metaphysics. In particular, Michael Della Rocca’s radically monistic
Parmenidean Ascent (2020) to Being is discussed as a profiling foil against which Hegel’s
Parmenidean descent from Being to negation, becoming and to all sorts of distinctions stands out. A
second foil for comparison is the “science without contrary” that Sebastian Rödl presented in
Self-Consciousness and Objectivity (2018). It turns out that Hegel is much more considerate of the
radical sceptic than Rödl. – All in all, the Science of Logic is portrayed here as Hegel’s theory of the
pre-temporal, purely logical evolution of logical space (the Hegelian Absolute). As such it is
designed by Hegel as the final nonstandard metaphysics which, if successful, would critically assess
all possible standard metaphysical theories, each of which fixes and immobilises a fluid stage in the
logical evolution and treats it as the static whole of logical space. – If successful, mind you, but
there are reasons to believe that Hegel does not achieve what he is aiming at.
Christian Krijnen: Heterologie oder Dialektik? Rickerts Lehre vom Ursprung des Denkens
im Spiegel der hegelschen Logik
Abstract:
With his heterology, the southwest German neo-Kantian Heinrich Rickert developed
a doctrine that proved to be groundbreaking not only for neo-Kantianism, but also for
the theory of subjectivity in postwar transcendental philosophy in the broad sense. Rickert’s
heterology is primarily concerned with the original structure of thought. In the discussion, the
alternative ‘Negation (Hegel) or Otherness (Rickert)?’ has become widespread. Since the discussion
of Hegel plays an important role for Rickert, heterology concerns at the same time the
relation of Hegel’s speculative idealism and (advanced) Kantian transcendental philosophy.
Accordingly, it has also had an impact on Hegel scholarship. However, until today and on the
whole, the debate is far from unanimous with regard to the validity of Rickert’s critique of
Hegel. In view of the almost deadlocked discussion, this study proposes a new interpretative
perspective. It focuses on the issue of formalism as a methodological problem. First, I outline the
problem of formalism, then I examine Rickert’s heterology for its formalism, subsequently I put
the thesis forward that Rickert’s heterology is, in Hegel’s words, a kind of external reflection.
This leads to the consequence that heterology lacks a logic of being: Rickert hastily moves from
the beginning of philosophy to the origin of thinking. Thus, unlike Hegel, Rickert provides only
an insufficient account of the very concepts with which he determines the origin of thought – an
Achilles’ heel of transcendental philosophy.
Ryôsuke Ohashi: Die Logik des Absoluten und die Logik des Leeren – oder: die Durchsichtigkeit
bei Hegel und das soku bei Nishitani
Abstract:
In this article, an attempt is made to compare, with reference to the theme
indicated in the title, Hegel’s logic, as the core of his entire philosophical speculation, and
Buddhist logic, which lays deep roots in the intellectual soil of the Kyoto School’s philosophy, as
represented by Keiji Nishitani. The term transparency, in the sense that it is used in Hegel’s logic,
and the soku of Buddhist logic stand as the focal point of this comparative treatment. In Hegel’s
Science of Logic, the term transparency first shows up at the end of the logic of essence and then
prominently in the logic of the Concept. The determinateness of the Concept-categories, and
indeed of all logical categories, is a thoroughly transparent shine, a difference that vanishes in its
positedness. This transparency itself is employed in the Hegelian logic without logical definition,
just like with the terms negation, transition, and mediation, as Kierkegaard once pointed out.
This element of transparency has nowhere been considered in past research on Hegel. Yet, this
element can be drawn out as the focal point in a comparative treatment of the Hegelian and
Buddhist logics. For in Buddhist logic, the word soku is used at such places where different states
of affairs are on level, and insofar as they are made transparent, with one another. For example,
there stands the most well-known saying of Mahayana Buddhism, which declares: “Emptiness is
soku appearance, appearance is soku emptiness.” At the point where these two terms intersect,
Hegel’s transparency and Nishitani’s soku, we see that the two overlap, and yet, at the same time,
they are separated by a gap in which what is peculiar to each becomes visible.
Ernst-Otto Onnasch: Fünf Briefe, eine Abschrift eines Goethe-Gedichts und ein Nürnberger Zeugnis
von G.W.F. Hegel
Abstract:
This paper presents four new letters by Hegel to (1) the wine merchant Ramann
(12 October 1802), to (2) his student and repetent in Berlin Friedrich Wilhelm Corové (12
December 1818) to (3) his friend Heinrich Beer (2 November 1828) and (4) the publisher
Friedrich Frommann (11 September 1818). A fifth letter to Friedrich Niethammer (11 September
1826) comes in a new and full transcription. A lost Hegel transcript of three poems by
Goethe resurfaced in a Dutch archive and is edited. Lastly a 1814 school certificate that Hegel
wrote in Nurnberg for his pupil Johann Christoph Sigmund Lechner has been found and edited.
Short introductions accompany each of the documents.

Birgit Sandkaulen ist Professorin für Philosophie an der Ruhr-Universität Bochum und Direktorin des Forschungszentrums für Klassische deutsche Philosophie/Hegel-Archiv. Sie ist Co-Projektleiterin des Akademievorhabens »Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi: Briefwechsel. Text – Kommentar – Wörterbuch Online« an der Sächsischen Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Leipzig und Mitherausgeberin der »Hegel-Studien«.

Erscheinungsdatum
Reihe/Serie Hegel-Studien ; 56
Verlagsort Hamburg
Sprache englisch; deutsch
Maße 155 x 235 mm
Gewicht 442 g
Einbandart kartoniert
Themenwelt Geisteswissenschaften Philosophie Philosophie der Neuzeit
Schlagworte Dialektik • Hegel, G. W. F. • Japanische Philosophie • Klassische Deutsche Philosophie • Logik, Hegelsche
ISBN-10 3-7873-4367-9 / 3787343679
ISBN-13 978-3-7873-4367-6 / 9783787343676
Zustand Neuware
Haben Sie eine Frage zum Produkt?
Mehr entdecken
aus dem Bereich